- HTML Translated Version -
Styles of Thought and Epistemological Approaches
Autora: Maryianela del Carmen Maita Guédez
Universidad de Los Andes Núcleo
Universitario “Dr. Pedro Rincón Gutiérrez”, ULA
mmaita@ula.ve; maryianelamaita@gmail.com
Táchira, Venezuela
Abstract
This paper begins with a historical reference whose purpose is to
distinguish the various philosophical positions given throughout the construction
of science. The path is divided into two periods, before and after the
seventeenth century, on the one hand, focuses on the Greek thought constituted
by the Aristotelian and Galilean traditions; On the other hand are presented
the great epistemological traditions: Rationalism and Empiricism. It continues
in the XIX with Augusto Comte who introduces the positivist approach to science
till the figure of Thomas Kuhn with the concept of paradigm. Then, it is about
the styles of thought and epistemological approaches due to each human being
has a particular way of approaching reality, learning, solving problems,
inferring, developing in their environment or following certain patterns that
resemble or differentiate them from others. Then the relationship between them
is established, proving that they are the support of any scientific revolution
exhibited in the course of history. Finally, it is concluded that all research
work acquires a value in the context of the belief system where it has been raised,
rather than within impositions of paradigms that establish supposedly
indisputable and universal schemes.
Keywords: epistemology; rationalism; empiricism; reasoning.
Date Received: 15-08-2017 |
Date Acceptance: 25-10-2017 |
Estilos de Pensamiento y Enfoques
Epistemológicos
Resumen
Este ensayo inicia con un referente histórico cuyo propósito es
distinguir las diversas posturas filosóficas dadas a lo largo de la
construcción de la ciencia. El recorrido se divide en dos épocas, antes y
después del siglo XVII, por una parte, se enfoca en el pensamiento griego
constituido por las tradiciones Aristotélicas y Galileanas; por la otra se
presentan las grandes tradiciones epistemológicas: el Racionalismo y el
Empirismo. Se continúa en el siglo XIX con Augusto Comte quien introduce el
enfoque positivista de la ciencia hasta llegar a la figura de Thomas Kuhn con
el concepto de paradigma. Seguidamente, se tratan los estilos de pensamiento y
enfoques epistemológicos pues cada ser humano tiene una forma particular de
abordar la realidad, aprender, resolver problemas, inferir, desenvolverse en su
entorno o seguir ciertos patrones que lo asemeja o diferencia de los otros.
Luego se establece la relación entre ambos, demostrándose que son el sustento
de cualquier revolución científica exhibida en el transcurso de la historia.
Finalmente se concluye que todo trabajo de investigación adquiere un valor en
el contexto del sistema de creencias donde ha sido planteado, más que dentro de
imposiciones de los paradigmas que establecen esquemas supuestamente
indiscutibles y universales.
Palabras clave: epistemología; racionalismo; empirismo; razonamiento.
Fecha de Recepción: 15-08-2017 |
Fecha de Aceptación: 25-10-2017 |
1. Introduction
Knowledge has been, throughout the history of science,
one of the great debates among philosophers, in which three beliefs are disputed:
the ontological ones that revolve around the nature of the phenomena, the
epistemological ones referred to the doubts how you can acquire, know,
communicate knowledge and methodological beliefs that focus on the interest in
the way in which the individual creates, modifies and interprets the world in
which he or she is. In other words, depending on how the subject who knows
(researcher) relates to the object of study, the very operation of knowing and
the information gathered about the object, the result can vary from a common
knowledge to a scientific knowledge.
For Martínez (2010a), knowledge is "the result of
a highly elaborated process of interaction between a sensory stimulus (visual,
auditory, olfactory, etc. or a content of our memory) and our entire internal
world of values, interests, beliefs, feelings, fears, etc." (p.176).
Therefore, the subject that investigates detects, raises and seeks solutions to
problematic situations that arise in the reality where it develops, permanently
maintaining a critical, reflective, sensitive action; as indicated by Morales
(2014), "under the attitude of amazement and admiration" (p.29),
before the object studied and the results obtained.
According to Arraga and Añez (2003a), the common
individual is the same as the researcher, who uses his cognitive processes:
learning styles (ways of organizing, storing information), thought styles (ways
they perceive, interpret, construct reality), as well as epistemological
approaches (position adopted to produce scientific knowledge) that predominates
when investigating.
In this essay the styles of thoughts, epistemological
approaches and the relation between both are treated to demonstrate that they
are the sustenance of any scientific revolution that takes place in the course
of history. In this sense begins with the conceptualization of the term
epistemology to then make a tour of the thinking of some relevant authors of
science, in order to distinguish the variations that have been presented in the
way of conceiving and doing science, opening the possibility to produce new
positions for scientific explanation that are not based exclusively on the
causal, teleological or hermeneutic.
2.
The philosophy of
science: in the search for a meeting point
The epistemology, or philosophy of science, for Bunge
(2002), "is the branch of philosophy that studies scientific research and
its product, knowledge" (p.21), taking into account the methods, nature
and structure for get it, validate it and socialize it. Jaramillo (2003), relates
it to the genesis of scientific knowledge, which through the objectivity of
them determine the ideological knowledge of the time, producing an impact and
cultural transformation in the institutions of a society. For his part, Vargas
(2015), believes that "supports the scientific reflection of any
discipline" (p.208).
From the above definitions, it can be asserted that
epistemology is the philosophy of science, is based on the critical reflection
of the foundations, principles and other aspects that support scientific
knowledge (reliable, verifiable, validated, socialized, reliable, universal)
generated in a discipline to give it the status of science, where postulates,
theories and laws that allow the development of humanity are formulated.
In this sense, science throughout its construction has
gone through different moments as if by different philosophical positions. Its
definition has been surrounded by controversies and variants, depending on
interests and perspectives; this is demonstrated by Mardones (1991a), in his
writing. In this regard, reviewing the history of the conception of science,
prior to the seventeenth century, you will find a predominance of the idea of
science inherited from Greek thought represented by the Aristotelian and Galilean
traditions.
For Aristotle (as quoted in Salgado, 2012), science is:
Knowledge of the
universal and of the necessary things, and there are some principles of the
demonstrable and of all science (since science is rational), the principle of
the scientific can not be neither science nor art nor prudence; because the scientific
is demonstrable (p.3).
This implies full confidence in the power of reason,
in other words, we come to the scientific explanation of a phenomenon or fact,
supported by the observation of the real world and the abstraction of the human
mind that is ordered and safely the demonstrations, therefore, are totally
opposed to the simple opinion. As argued by (Mardones, 1991b), Aristotle
demanded that the cause of a phenomenon should cover four aspects: the formal
cause, the material cause, the efficient cause and the final cause, emphasizing
the final cause, revealing teleological explanations.
Sandín (2003a), documents that the Galilean tradition
poses a new "scientific world" in which Aristotle's teleological
worldview is rejected and a mainly pragmatic and mechanistic vision of the
world appears, in which experience as a source of knowledge will have an
emphasis higher. The precursors of this position are Francis Bacon (1561-1626),
who picks up the propensity of concrete facts with an attempt to dominate
nature. Galileo Galilei (1564-1642), according to (Mardones, 1991c), represents
"the new mentality that changes the qualitative physical explanations of
Aristotle by the mathematical formulations of Archimedes" (p.25).
Consequently, mathematics will be the fundamental instrument for the scientific
explanation of a phenomenon and whose explanations will take the forms of
causal hypotheses that are determined by experimental analysis.
Likewise, (Sandín, 2003b), indicates that from the
XVII century the term idealism arose to designate the Platonic theory in which
the possibility was exposed that man could only know "ideas",
subjective and private objects of the human mind. From this century until the
figure of Kant (1724-1804), with its philosophical attitude called Criticism,
European philosophers are circumscribed in two major epistemological
traditions: Rationalism in which continental thinkers such as Descartes
(1596-1650), Leibniz ( 1646-1716) and Spinoza (1632-1677) and Empiricism
represented by English authors such as Locke (1632-1704), Hume (1711-1776) and
Berkeley (1685-1753).
In the rationalist conception of knowledge, knowledge
is constituted by reason, being this the only principle and foundation of true
knowledge, because only this produces clear, universal and undoubtedly certain
ideas. This is what Descartes (2010) affirms in his Discourse on Method:
"awake or asleep, we should never allow ourselves to be persuaded except by
the evidence of reason" (p.65). Use mathematics as a model and
intellectual intuition as a source of knowledge.
In the empiricist tradition, true knowledge comes from
experience, in other words, it defends as a form of knowledge the detailed
verification of facts through observation, the senses, perceptions and
sensations are the means through which the ideas in the mind.
The greatest exponent of this position Locke (2005a),
in the original document of 1689, ensures that "all ideas come from
sensation or reflection. Suppose, then, that the mind is, as they say, a blank
paper, clean of all inscription, without any idea "(page 36). This means
that human reason is empty before receiving experience. For (Locke, 2005b),
there are three elementary forms of knowledge correlated with the known object;
Padrón (2014a), expresses them as "intuition (experience, introspection,
understanding), demonstration (reasoning, argumentation, explanation) and
sensation (sensory capture, observation, instrumentation)" (p.1).
Going back to the 19th century, we find that Auguste
Comte (1798-1857), introduces the positivist approach of science to designate
scientific knowledge in which social, historical, and economic science is
intended, among others. Comte (2004), in his Positive Philosophy Course
published from 1830 to 1842, states that the first great result of positive
philosophy is "the manifestation by the experience of the laws that
accompany in their execution our intellectual functions and, therefore, the
rigorous knowledge of the general rules suitable to proceed with security in
the search for the truth" (p.52).
In Comte's approach, true scientific knowledge, which
allows us to discover the reality of what is being studied, is that obtained
through empirical observation, experimentation and induction, leaving aside
theological and metaphysical conceptions for not showing facts such as they are
perceived by the senses. In this approach, verifiability is the criterion for
distinguishing empirical sciences from other types of knowledge, based on the
Galilean tradition of science, following the ideal typification of mathematical
physics and trying to frame all knowledge with scientific pretensions under the
same method.
Additionally, the author in reference establishes as
the aim of the positivist philosophy "to summarize in a body of
homogeneous doctrine the totality of the acquired knowledge, related to the
different orders of natural phenomena" (p.62).
The Circle of Vienna, in the first decades of the
twentieth century, composed of the followers of Hume's Empiricism, are the
creators of Logical Positivism, also called Neopositivism or Logical
Empiricism. They set their interest in introducing, to the study of philosophy,
methods and mathematical precision, basing the bases that linked truth and
meaning, in order to distinguish between what is science and what is not. They
excluded the metaphysics, theory and ethics of genuine human knowledge.
Positivism, which prevailed for more than three
centuries, soon had its detractors, and an anti-positivist tendency called
Hermeneutics was forged in the German sphere, in which the pretensions of the
positivism of methodological monism, of predictive and causalist zeal, were
rejected. the reduction of reason to instrumental reason and the imposition of
mathematical physics as the mechanism of all scientific explanation.
For their part, the philosophers of the Frankfurt school
created in 1923, began to question Positivism, establishing what was later
called Critical Theory, characterized by its critical consciousness, worth the
redundancy, which points out that the experiences lived may be distorted by a
false ideology or conscience. Likewise, according to (Martínez, 2010b),
physicists, psychologists of Gestalt, linguists, biologists and philosophers of
science, of the new scientific rationality, showed their dissatisfaction with
linear rationality and the need to replace the model axiomatic of thinking,
reasoning and demonstrating, where a logical-mathematical ideal prevails, by
"a logic that accommodates the authentic and more empirical reality of the
world in which we live and with which we interact, of a world where there are
real inconsistencies, inconsistencies logical and even conceptual
contradictions" (p.175).
Likewise, Popper (1902-1994), begins to pay attention
to the problem of social sciences, this is highlighted in his paper entitled the
logic of social sciences. Popper (1978), states that the method of these lies
in testing the possible solutions to problems, because scientific knowledge is
hypothetical and conjectural, in which the product of knowledge is more an act
of invention than discovery; Arbitrary sketches are made of the theories that
require a verification and in the cases that a scientific hypothesis can not be
verified, the verification is not used but falsifiability, which should lead
the scientist to reject them. Induction does not constitute a sufficiently
secure basis to explain the validity of scientific theories, but relies on the
deduction.
The figure of Thomas Kuhn (1922-1996), comes to take a
historicist turn in the philosophy of science and continued by Imre Lakatos
(1922-1974), for whom the process of falsifiability does not seem as simple and
logical as it gives to understand Popper, for which the Popperian design of
conjectures and refutations has to be abandoned, maintaining rational criteria
for the substitution or elimination of research programs. Kuhn showed the
ineffectiveness of the Popperian criterion of falsifiability. It taught how
science really works, considering it an organized activity, possessing certain
models to control results, which depend not only on logical or intellectual
factors but also on historical and social factors, paying attention to the
process by which scientific knowledge is obtained .
Finally, it should be noted that the paradigm concept
was generalized after 1962 in Kuhn's work "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions".
For Kuhn (1962), a paradigm "are universally recognized scientific
achievements that, for a time, provide models of problems and solutions to a
scientific community" (p.13); In other words, it refers to the way
scientists conceive their area of interest, the problems to be studied, the
methods to be used, among others; within your disciplinary area.
3. Thinking
styles
Each human being has a particular way of approaching
reality, learning, solving problems, inferring, developing in their environment
or following certain patterns that resemble or differentiate them from others. This
is primarily due to thought styles, which are formed before birth and gradually
consolidates as the individual interacts with their environment.
In conceptualizing the styles of thought, Valadez
(2009) reveals as distinctive aspects the way in which people focus their
tasks. Depending on the situations that are faced, a specific style will be
manifested, therefore, there are differences in the intensity of the style that
go according to the identification of the person with this one. They are
variable styles, in fact they can be modified throughout life. In short, for
the author, the style of thinking refers to a capacity or aptitude and not a
skill.
On the other hand, López and Martín (2010), express:
"Thinking styles are the ways in which people prefer to use the
intellectual capacities available to them" (p.255), that is, it is related
to how intelligence is used more than at the level you have of it.
In this essay we follow the approaches of (Padrón,
2014b), for whom thinking styles represent the cognitive personality, are
responsible for the way we see things, know them and control them. They are
oriented towards three factors: senses (controlled observation), brain
(reasoning) and heart (experiences and introspections).
Without a doubt, the senses, brain and heart coexist
in the individual, they are inseparable, but in each circumstance that is
presented, information management or problem solving, one of them tends to be
the one that identifies us. In this respect, thinking styles are:
·
Inductive - Concrete: the individuals with predominance in this style of
thought are pragmatic, they are guided mainly by the senses and the detailed
observation of the world that surrounds them, this is the premise to verify the
facts, which is why they require direct contact with the object of study.
·
Deductive - Abstract: in this case, the individuals start from general
knowledge by means of the derivation to construct new concepts, the main source
to achieve it is the reasoning, the argumentation, the deduction. They are
theoretical and idealistic, prefer the information implicit directly in the
object of study.
·
Intuitive - Experiential: they are based on thought, introspection, sensitivity
for the search for solutions, where internal experiences have a great value.
4. Epistemological
approaches
The aforementioned author documents the
epistemological approaches as scientific knowledge and the way to produce it,
which are conviction systems of the highest level of cognitive depth,
universal, that have a presence in the creation of scientific knowledge as
follows:
·
Empiricism: called medical approach, is based on induction
(controlled experience, explanation). Trust sensory perception. Look for
patterns of repetition that are expressed statistically.
·
Rationalism: the rationalist approach uses deduction as a method
of finding (logical modeling, explanation). Its main postulate is the trust in
pure reasoning. It pursues broad basic universal structures.
·
Experientialism: also called experientialist approach, is based on
intuition (lived experience, understanding). It fixes the attention on the
sociocultural symbolisms, aided by a verbalized instrument of open options.
Although epistemological approaches are associated
with the production of scientific knowledge, these come from the styles of thought,
both occur in the privileged holistic center of the human being. On this,
(Arraga and Añez, 2003b), they affirm that "they are of a cognitive
nature; that is, they are mental processes that take place in the brain" (p.36),
who is responsible for processing information, managing it and solving
problems.
The relationship between thought styles and
epistemological approaches is given by several aspects, for example, the focus
of attention, the ways of approaching reality, the channel that is used for
contact with reality, the predominant language, the object of study, among
others.
Table 1 shows the basic relationships between the
thinking styles and the epistemological approaches considered in this essay.
Table 1. Relations between thought styles and epistemological
approaches.
SEE
IN THE ORIGINAL VERSION
Source: Adaptation Based on Arraga y Añez (2003) and Padrón
(2014).
As indicated in the first section, the philosophers of
science have subscribed, according to the source of knowledge of a research, to
two epistemological traditions: Rationalism and Empiricism. In the same way,
two ontological distinctions are presented, oriented to the form and nature of
reality, taking into account the role played by the subject that investigates
the object under investigation or the reality studied. These
are Idealism and Realism.
In idealism, reality is an idea, it is based on the
understanding and interpretation of the object of study as the result of
thinking; Experience and interaction prevail. Realism, as a position
antagonistic to idealism, conditions thinking, therefore, reality is
independent of our consciousness, what we perceive through the senses
predominates. It is based on the explanation; Through experience you come to
knowledge.
Based on these criteria of the subject-object
relationship and the source of knowledge (Padrón, 2014c), consider 4
well-differentiated epistemological approaches can be refined, with the
consolidation of conceptual pairs Empiricism / Rationalism and Realism /
Idealism. Table 2 shows how ontological and epistemological distinctions
intersect: Empiricism - Idealism, Empiricism - Realism, Rationalism - Idealism,
Rationalism - Realism, to form other approaches.
Table 2. Epistemological approaches.
SEE IN THE ORIGINAL VERSION
Source: Padrón (2014)
4.1. Experientialist-experientialist
approach: the subject, through
field work, has a leading role in obtaining information about what you want to
know. In this way, researcher and object of study are interactively related and
can inevitably be influenced, consequently, the results will be mediated by the
values of the researcher. Habermas (1986), in his work Science and Technique
as Ideology, original document of 1968, demonstrates the impossibility of
science being an activity free of frequently confronted values and interests.
At the
intersection, from table 2, Empiricism / Idealism; the methodology is
dialogical and dialectical, since the transactional nature of the research
requires a dialogue between the subject and the object studied, which must have
a dialectical essence to transform the unknown and the erroneous into
knowledge, understanding the actions necessary to effect the change before the
problem that it tries to solve. This approach would include ethnographic work,
participatory action research, ethnomethodological, coexistence designs, among
others.
4.2. Empiricist-Inductivist
approach: the researcher relies
on sensory perception and pursues patterns of regularity, through field work,
seeks to measure, explain, control, predict. It supposes the existence of an
apprehensible reality driven by unalterable natural laws and mechanisms.
Subject and object of study are independent entities, consequently, they should
not be influenced by one another; some influence, in either direction, threatens
the validity of the investigation. Additionally, its methodology is
experimental and manipulative in the sense that the hypotheses or questions
posed are presented as propositions subject to an empirical test for
verification. The historical example that dominated science for a long time was
Positivism.
4.3. Vivencialist-Interpretative
approach: in this approach based on rationality, as a source of knowledge,
meaning is not discovered, but is constructed; it emerges from the interaction
with reality and is based on specific experiences, ideas or varied and
intangible mental representations, which depend on the individuals or groups
that interact. It is contrasted with interpretativism in a way that seeks to
understand and question at the same time. In the same way that the
Empiricism-Idealism approach, the researcher and the researched are
interactively linked in such a way that the findings are influenced, therefore,
the intersubjective consensus and active validation of those who produce
knowledge through an exchange come into play. dialectical. A critical example
is the critical theory.
4.4. Rationalist-Deductivist
Approach: is based on pure
reason, access to knowledge, its production and validation are linked to the
construction of abstractions that reveal the behavior of the facts (material
and human), the field works are not discarded, but it relies primarily on
interpretation and on systems of reasoning that go from the general to the
particular (deduction) with logical-mathematical modeling. Falsationism is one of
the historical examples of this approach.
5. Final
reflections
In solving problems of daily life and information
management, thinking styles are the main protagonist, since they are an
inherent part of the human being. Although there are different classifications
of the styles of thought, here the one suggested by José Padrón was followed,
in which the brain, senses and heart converge; that depending on the
circumstances one of the three styles may prevail: Inductive - Concrete,
Deductive - Abstract, Intuitive - Experiential.
Now, in the field of research and science, we speak of
epistemological approaches which have a correlation with the styles of thought,
therefore, they have always existed: since man is man and science is science,
they are the sustenance of any scientific revolution that has occurred in the
course of history.
From a certain point of view, there are at least three
broad and universal epistemological approaches, namely, the medicinal approach,
the experientialist approach and the rationalist approach, which have been
disputed throughout history to control what is or is not The science. However,
making a cross between ontological distinctions and epistemological
distinctions, four approaches are refined: Vivencialist - Experientialist, Empiricist
- Inductivist, Vivencialist - Interpretativist, Rationalist - Deductivist.
The brief tour of the thought of some relevant authors
of the history of science, presented in this essay, leads us to point out that,
thanks to thought styles and epistemological approaches, there is not a single
theory that meets all the necessary requirements to do science, on the
contrary, there are multiple ways of approaching and solving problems, as well
as positions, perspectives or methodologies.
Each position has its followers and detractors, but
this gives the possibility of producing new alternatives for scientific
explanation that are not based exclusively on the causal, teleological or
hermeneutic but on the contrary open paths for complementarity for the benefit of
obtaining knowledge scientific through justified methodological concretions
that respond to the requirements of credibility, reliability and questioning of
the results.
Finally, in view of the controversies elucidated,
around the epistemological debate, about which are the best ways and
perspectives to do science, it is convenient that in a research work the
convictions are identified where a certain search is located. Defining this
epistemological framework is a key element to analyze and evaluate both the
research process and the documented representation of the results to facilitate
the estimation of research quality, since all research acquires a value in the
context of the system of beliefs in which it has been proposed, rather than
within the impositions of scientific revolutions (Paradigms) that establish
supposedly indisputable and universal schemes.
6. References
Árraga, M. & Añez, A. (2003a,b). Aprendizaje, enfoques epistemológicos y
estilos de pensamiento. Encuentro Educacional. Vol. 10. N° 1, págs. 23-37.
Recuperado de: http://www.produccioncientificaluz.org/index.php/encuentro/article/viewFile/907/909
Bunge, M. (2002). Epistemología. Curso de actualización.
México D.F, México: Siglo XXI Editores.
Comte, A. (2004). Curso de filosofía positiva. Lecciones 1 y
2. Discurso sobre el espíritu positivo. Recuperado de:
https://es.scribd.com/doc/81133541/Curso-de-Filosofia-Positiva-Comte
Descartes, R. (2010). Discurso del Método. Recuperado de:
Habermas, J. (1986). Ciencia y técnica como ideología.
Recuperado de:
Jaramillo, L. (2003). ¿Qué es Epistemología? Mi mirar epistemológico y el progreso de la
ciencia. Cinta Moebio 18, págs. 174-178.
Recuperado de: http://www.revistas.uchile.cl/index.php/CDM/article/viewFile/26135/27433
Kuhn, T. (1962). La estructura de las revoluciones científicas. Breviarios. Fondo de Cultura Económica.
Locke, J. (2005). Filosofía de John Locke. Ensayo sobre el entendimiento humano.
Recuperado de: https://getafe.es/wp-content/uploads/Locke_John-Ensayo_sobre_el_entendimiento_humano.pdf
López, O. & Martín,
R. (2010). Estilos
de pensamiento y creatividad. Anales de Psicología, vol.
26, núm. 2, págs. 254-258. Universidad de Murcia, España. Recuperado de: http://www.redalyc.org/pdf/167/16713079008.pdf
Mardones, J. (1991a,b,c). Filosofía de las ciencias humanas y sociales.
Nota histórica de una polémica
incesante. Universidad Nacional Abierta. Barcelona: Anthropos Promat.
Recuperado de: http://dip.una.edu.ve/mead/filosofia/paginas/mardones1.pdf
Martínez, M. (2010a,b). Bases de la Epistemología a Comienzos del
Siglo XXI. Foundations of
Epistemology in Early XXI Century. Revista IIPSI, Facultad de Psicología UNMSM. vol. 13
núm. 1. Recuperado de: http://sisbib.unmsm.edu.pe/bvrevistas/investigacion_psicologia/v13_n1/pdf/a11.pdf
Morales, J. (2014). Propuesta
de una filosofía de las ciencias administrativas y gerenciales desde la praxis
y cotidianidad del gerente venezolano en su contexto. (Tesis doctoral, Universidad
de Carabobo, Valencia, Venezuela). Recuperado de http://mriuc.bc.uc.edu.ve/bitstream/handle/123456789/579/jmorales.pdf?sequence=4
Padrón, J. (2014a,b,c). Notas sobre enfoques epistemológicos,
estilos de pensamiento y paradigmas. DOI: 10.13140/RG.2.2.22714.08642
Popper, K. (1978). La Lógica de las Ciencias Sociales.
Recuperado de: http://epistemologiadelascienciassociales.sociales.uba.ar/files/2013/04/La_l%C3%B3gica_de_las_ciencias_sociales_Popper_E_A_FFyL.pdf
Salgado, S. (2012). La filosofía de Aristóteles. Cuadernos
Duererías, Serie Historia de la Filosofía núm. 12, ISSN: 1989-7774. Recuperado
de: http://guindo.pntic.mec.es/~ssag0007/filosofica/aristoteles-duererias.pdf
Sandín, M. (2003a,b). Investigación Cualitativa en Educación. Fundamentos y Tradiciones.
Madrid, España: McGraw-Hill.
Valadez, M. (2009). Estilos de aprendizaje y estilos de pensamiento:
precisiones conceptuales. Revista de Educación y Desarrollo, núm.
11, págs. 19-30. octubre-diciembre. Recuperado de: http://www.cucs.udg.mx/revistas/edu_desarrollo/anteriores/11/011_Huizar.pdf
Vargas, J. (2015). Enfoque dialógico a la epistemología de las Ciencias Administrativas. Revista Debates, Porto Alegre. vol. 9. núm. 1,
págs. 205-222. Recuperado de: http://www.seer.ufrgs.br/debates/article/viewFile/50173/33508
Maryianela
del Carmen Maita Guédez
e-mail: mmaita@ula.ve; maryianelamaita@gmail.com
Born in the state of Barinas, Venezuela. Bachelor of
Education in Computer Science and Mathematics graduated from the Universidad
Católica del Táchira (1996). He has a Master's Degree in Mathematics,
Mathematics Education from the Universidad Nacional Experimental del Táchira (2005).
PhD in Management Sciences from UNEFA Táchira. She works as a professor in the
Associate Category of the Universidad de Los Andes Núcleo Universitario “Dr.
Pedro Rincón Gutiérrez” Táchira, in the Computer and Information department. He
has published his teaching and research experience in various refereed
journals. Currently accredited in the Innovation and Research Stimulus Program
(PEII).
The content of this manuscript is
disseminated under a Creative
Commons License Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International
-
Original
Version in Spanish -
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.29394/Scientific.issn.2542-2987.2018.3.7.19.374-393